SlideShare a Scribd company logo
KNOWLEDGE REPRESENTATION
&
PREDICATE LOGIC
Amey D.S.Kerkar,
Asst.Professor, Computer Engineering Dept.
Don Bosco College of Engineering,
Fatorda-Goa.
• To solve complex problems we need:
1. Large amount of knowledge
2. Mechanism for representation and manipulation
of existing knowledge to create new solution.
Knowledge Representation
– Facts: Things we want to represent. Truth in some
relevant world.
– Representation of facts.
Representation and Mapping
Facts
Internal
Representations
English
Representations
reasoning
programs
English
understanding
English
generation
Initial
facts
Internal
representations
of initial facts
desired real reasoning
forward
representation
mapping
Final
facts
Internal
representations
of final facts
backward
representation
mapping
operation
of program
5
Representation and Mapping
• Spot is a dog
• Every dog has a tail
Spot has a tail
6
Representation and Mapping
• Spot is a dog
dog(Spot)
• Every dog has a tail
x: dog(x)  hastail(x)
hastail(Spot)
Spot has a tail
• Fact-representation mapping is not one-to-one.
• Good representation can make a reasoning program
trivial.
The Multilated Checkerboard Problem
“Consider a normal checker board from which two
squares, in opposite corners, have been removed.
The task is to cover all the remaining squares exactly
with donimoes, each of which covers two squares. No
overlapping, either of dominoes on top of each other or
of dominoes over the boundary of the multilated board
are allowed.
Can this task be done?” 7
8
Representation and Mapping
No. black squares
= 30
No. white square
= 32
Good Knowledge representation should exhibit:
1. Representational adequacy-
Ability to represent all kinds of knowledge that are needed in the
domain.
2. Inferential adequacy-
Ability to manipulate representational structures such that new
knowledge can be derived/inferred from the old.
3. Inferential efficiency-
Ability to incorporate additional information into an existing
knowledge base that can be used to focus the attention of inference
mechanisms in the most promising direction.
4. Acquisitional efficiency-
Ability to easily acquire new information. 9
10
Approaches to KR
1. Simple relational knowledge:
• Provides very weak inferential capabilities.
• May serve as the input to powerful inference engines.
Fails to infer “which right handed player can best face a
particular bowler” .
Player Height Weight handed
Peter 6-0 180 right
Ajay 5-10 170 left
John 6-2 215 left
Vickey 6-3 205 right
11
Approaches to KR
Inheritable knowledge:
• Objects are organized into classes and classes are
organized in a generalization hierarchy.
• Inheritance is a powerful form of inference, but not
adequate.
• Ex. Property inheritance inference mechanism.
Adult male Person
isa
Peter
instance
Right
handed
Tata Consultancy
Works_at
12
Approaches to KR
Inferential knowledge:
• Facts represented in a logical form, which facilitates
reasoning.
• An inference engine is required.
ex. 1. “Marcus is a man”
2. “All men are mortal”
Implies:
3. “Marcus is mortal”
13
Approaches to KR
Procedural knowledge:
• Representation of “how to make it” rather than “what
it is”.
• May have inferential efficiency, but no inferential
adequacy and acquisitional efficiency.
• Ex. Writing LISP programs
14
Issues in KR
1. Important Attributes: Isa and instance attributes.
2. Relationships among attributes: inverses, existence in a Isa
hierarchy, single-valued attributes, techniques for reasoning
about values.
3.Choosing the Granularity: High-level facts may not be adequate
for inference. Low-level primitives may require a lot of storage.
• Ex: “john spotted sue”
[representation: spotted(agent(john),object(sue))]
Q1: “who spotted sue?” Ans1: “john”.
Q2: “Did john see sue?” Ans2: NO ANSWER!!!!
• Add detailed fact: spotted(x,y)-->saw(x,y) then Ans2: “Yes”.
• 4.Representing Set of Objects:
• 5. finding the right structure as needed.:
Ex: word “fly” can have multiple meanings:
1. “John flew to new york”
2. “John flew into a rage” [idiom]
3. “john flew a kite”
SELF: Please read frame problem pg. 96-97, Rich & Knight,3rd
edition.
15
Propositional logic
• Statements used in mathematics.
• Proposition :is a declarative sentence whose value is
either true or false.
Examples:
• “The sky is blue.” [Atomic Proposition]
• “The sky is blue and the plants are green.”
[Molecular/Complex Proposition]
• “Today is a rainy day” [Atomic Proposition]
• “Today is Sunday” [Atomic Proposition]
• “ 2*2=4” [Atomic Proposition]
16
Terminologies in propositional algebra:
Statement: sentence that can be true/false.
Properties of statement:
 Satisfyability: a sentence is satisfyable if there is an
interpretation for which it is true.
Eg.”we wear woollen cloths”
 Contradiction: if there is no interpretation for which
sentence is true.
Eg. “Japan is capital of India”
 Validity: a sentence is valid if it is true for every
interpretation.
Eg. “Delhi is the capital of India” 17
Inference rules:
18
19
INFERENCE RULES IN PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC
1. Idempotent rule:
P ˄ P ==> P
P ˅ P ==> P
2. Commutative rule:
P ˄ Q ==> Q ˄ P
P ˅ Q ==> Q ˅ P
3.Associative rule:
P ˄ (Q ˄ R) ==> (P ˄ Q) ˄ R
P ˅ (Q ˅ R) ==> (P ˅ Q) ˅ R
20
4. Distributive Rule:
P ˅ (Q ˄ R) ==> (P ˅ Q) ˄ (P ˅ R)
P ˄ (Q ˅ R) ==> (P ˄ Q) ˅ (P ˄ R)
5. De-Morgan’s Rule:
‫(ך‬P ˅ Q) ==> ‫ך‬P ˄ ‫ך‬Q
‫ך‬ (P ˄ Q) ==> ‫ך‬ P ˅ ‫ך‬Q
6. Implication elimination:
P  Q => ‫ך‬P ˅ Q
21
7. Bidirectional Implication elimination:
( P  Q ) ==> ( P  Q ) ˄ (Q  P)
8. Contrapositive rule:
P  Q => ‫ך‬P  ‫ך‬Q
9. Double Negation rule:
‫(ך‬ ‫ך‬P) => P
10. Absorption Rule:
P ˅ ( P ˄ Q) => P
P ˄ ( P ˅ Q) => P
22
11.Fundamental identities:
P ˄ ‫ך‬ p => F [contradiction]
P ˅ ‫ך‬P => T [Tautology]
P ˅ T => P
P ˅ F => P
P ˅ ‫ך‬ T => P
P ˄ F => F
P ˄ T => P
23
12. Modus Ponens:
If P is true and PQ then we can infer Q is also true.
P
PQ
__________
Hence, Q
13. Modus Tollens:
If ‫ך‬P is true and PQ then we can infer ‫ך‬Q .
‫ך‬P
PQ
__________
Hence, ‫ך‬Q 24
14. Chain rule:
If pq and qr then pr
15. Disjunctive Syllogism:
if ‫ך‬p and p˅q we can infer q is true.
16. AND elimination:
Given P and Q are true then we can deduce P and Q
seperately: P ˄ Q  P
P ˄ Q Q
25
17. AND introduction:
Given P and Q are true then we deduce P ˄ Q
18. OR introduction:
Given P and Q are true then we can deduce P and Q
separately:
P P ˅ Q
Q P ˅ Q
26
• Example:
“I will get wet if it rains and I go out of the house”
Let Propositions be:
W : “I will get wet “
R : “it rains “
S : “I go out of the house”
(S ˄ R)  W
27
28
Using Propositional Logic
Representing simple facts
It is raining
RAINING
It is sunny
SUNNY
It is windy
WINDY
If it is raining, then it is not sunny
RAINING  SUNNY
Normal Forms in propositional Logic
1. Conjunctive normal form (CNF):
e.g. ( P ˅ Q ˅ R ) ˄ (P ˅ Q ) ˄ (P ˅ R ) ˄ P
It is conjunction (˄) of disjunctions (˅)
Where disjunctions are:
1. ( P ˅ Q ˅ R )
2. (P ˅ Q )
3. (P ˅ R ) clauses
4. P
29
2. Disjunctive normal form (DNF):
e.g. ( P ˄ Q ˄ R ) ˅ (P ˄ Q ) ˅ (P ˄ R ) ˅ P
It is disjunction (˅) of conjunctions (˄)
30
Procedure to convert a statement to CNF
1. Eliminate implications and biconditionals using formulas:
• ( P  Q ) ==> ( P  Q ) ˄ (Q  P)
• P  Q => ‫ך‬P ˅ Q
2. Apply De-Morgan’s Law and reduce NOT symbols so as to bring negations
before the atoms. Use:
• ‫(ך‬P ˅ Q) ==> ‫ך‬P ˄ ‫ך‬Q
• ‫ך‬ (P ˄ Q) ==> ‫ך‬ P ˅ ‫ך‬Q
3. Use distributive and other laws & equivalent formulas to obtain Normal forms.
31
Conversion to CNF example
Q. Convert into CNF : ( ( PQ )R )
Solution:
Step 1: ( ( PQ )R ) ==> ( ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q)R)
==> ‫ך‬ ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q) ˅ R
Step 2: ‫ך‬ ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q) ˅ R ==> (P ˄ ‫ך‬ Q ) ˅ R
Step 3: (P ˄ ‫ך‬ Q ) ˅ R ==> ( P ˅ R ) ˄ (‫ך‬ Q ˅ R )
CNF
32
Resolution in propositional logic
Proof by Refutation / contradiction.
• Used for theorem proving / rule of inference.
• Method: Say we have to prove proposition A
• Assume A to be false i.e. ‫ך‬A
• Continue solving the algorithm starting from ‫ך‬A
• If you get a contradiction (F) at the end it means your initial
assumption i.e. ‫ך‬A is false and hence proposition A must
be true.
• Clause: disjunction of literals is called clause.
33
• How it works?
• E.g. “ If it is Hot then it is Humid. If it is humid then it will rain. It
is hot.” prove that “ it will rain.”
• Solution:
• Let us denote these statements with propositions H,O and R:
– H: “ It is humid”.
– O: “ It is Hot”. And R: “It will rain”.
• Formulas corresponding to the sentences are:
• 1. “if it is hot then it is humid” [ OH] ==> ‫ך‬O ˅ H
• 2. “If it is humid then it will rain”. [ HR] ==> ‫ך‬H ˅ R
• 3. “ It is Hot” [ O ] ==> O
•
• To prove: R.
34
• Let us assume “it will NOT rain” [ ‫ך‬R ]
• [ ‫ך‬R ] [ ‫ך‬H ˅ R]
‫ך‬H [ ‫ך‬O ˅ H]
‫ך‬ O O
E [EMPTY CLAUSE / CONTRADICTION ]
35
• Since an empty clause ( E ) has been deduced we say that
our assumption is wrong and hence we have proved:
“It will rain”
Using Prepositional Logic:
• Theorem proving is decidable BUT
• It Cannot represent objects and quantification.
• Hence we go for PREDICATE LOGIC
36
PREDICATE LOGIC
• Can represent objects and quantification
• Theorem proving is semi-decidable
37
Representing simple facts (Preposition)
“SOCRATES IS A MAN”
SOCRATESMAN ---------1
“PLATO IS A MAN”
PLATOMAN ---------2
Fails to capture relationship between Socrates and man.
We do not get any information about the objects involved
Ex:
if asked a question : “who is a man?” we cannot get
answer.
Using Predicate Logic however we can represent above
facts as: Man(Socretes) and Man(Plato)
38
39
Using Predicate Logic
1. Marcus was a man.
man(Marcus)
40
Using Predicate Logic
2. Marcus was a Pompeian.
Pompeian(Marcus)
• Quantifiers:
• 2 types:-
• Universal quantifier ()
• x: means “for all” x
• It is used to represent phrase “ for all”.
• It says that something is true for all possible values of
a variable.
• Ex. “ John loves everyone”
•
41
• Quantifiers:
• 2 types:-
• Universal quantifier ()
• x: means “for all” x
• It is used to represent phrase “ for all”.
• It says that something is true for all possible values of
a variable.
• Ex. “ John loves everyone”
x: loves(John , x)
42
• Existential quantifier (  ):
• Used to represent the fact “ there exists some”
• Ex:
• “some people like reading and hence they gain good
knowledge”
 x: { [person(x)  like (x , reading)] gain(x, knowledge) }
• “lord Haggins has a crown on his head”
•  x: crown(x)  onhead (x , Haggins)
43
Nested Quantifiers
• We can use both  and  seperately
• Ex: “ everybody loves somebody ”
x: y: loves ( x , y)
• Connection between  and 
• “ everyone dislikes garlic”
 x:  like ( x , garlic )
 This can be also said as:
“there does not exists someone who likes garlic”
 x: like (x, garlic)
44
3. All Romans were either loyal to Caesar or hated him.
x: Roman(x)  loyalto (x, Caesar)  hate(x, Caesar)
4. Every one is loyal to someone.
x: y: loyalto(x, y) y: x: loyalto(x, y)
5. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.
x: y: person(x)  ruler(y)  tryassassinate(x, y)
 loyalto(x, y)
45
46
6. “All Pompeians were Romans”
x: Pompeian(x)  Roman(x)
8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar.
tryassassinate(Marcus, Caesar)
Some more examples
• “all indoor games are easy”
x: indoor_game( x)  easy(x)
• “Rajiv likes only cricket”
Like(Rajiv, Cricket)
• “Any person who is respected by every person is a king”
x:y: { person(x)  person(y)  respects (y ,x) king( x)}
47
• “god helps those who helps themselves”
x: helps( god, helps(x , x))
• “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone”
x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]
everyone who loves all animals
z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x
Thus the predicate sentence is:
x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ]
48
• “god helps those who helps themselves”
x: helps( god, helps(x , x))
• “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone”
x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]
everyone who loves all animals
z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x
Thus the predicate sentence is:
x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ]
• “god helps those who helps themselves”
x: helps( god, helps(x , x))
• “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone”
x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]
everyone who loves all animals
z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x
Thus the predicate sentence is:
x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ]
Computable functions and predicates
• “ Marcus was born in 40 A.D”
Born( Marcus, 40)
• “ All Pompeians died when volcano erupted in 79 A.D”
Erupted(volcano, 79)  x: [ Pompeian (x )  Died (x , 79)]
• “ no mortal lives longer than 150 years”
• How to solve ?
• let t1 is time instance 1 and t2 is time instance 2
• We use computable function gt( … , ….) which computes
greater than.
x: t1: t2: mortal (x)  born ( x, t1)  gt( t2 –t1, 150 ) 
dead ( x, t2)
49
Resolution algorithm in predicate
logic
• Proof by refutation.
• INPUT: Predicate sentences in clausal form (CNF)
• (See conversion algo on next slide)
• Algorithm steps :-
Convert all the propositions of KB to clause form (S).
2. Negate  and convert it to clause form. Add it to S.
3. Repeat until either a contradiction is found or no progress can be made.
a. Select two clauses (  P) and (  P).
b. Add the resolvent (  ) to S.
50
51
Conversion to Clause Form
1. Eliminate .
P  Q  P  Q
2. Reduce the scope of each  to a single term.
(P  Q)  P  Q
(P  Q)  P  Q
x: P  x: P
x: p  x: P
 P  P
3. Standardize variables so that each quantifier binds a unique variable.
(x: P(x))  (x: Q(x)) 
(x: P(x))  (y: Q(y))
52
4. Move all quantifiers to the left without changing their relative
order.
(x: P(x))  (y: Q(y)) 
x: y: (P(x)  (Q(y))
5. Eliminate  (Skolemization).
x: P(x)  P(c) Skolem constant
x: y P(x, y)  x: P(x, f(x)) Skolem function
6. Drop .
x: P(x)  P(x)
7. Convert the formula into a conjunction of disjuncts.
(P  Q)  R  (P  R)  (Q  R)
8. Create a separate clause corresponding to each conjunct.
9. Standardize apart the variables in the set of obtained
clauses.
53
• Example of conversion:
x:  [ Roman (x)  ( Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar))]
After step 1: i.e. elimination of  and  the above stmt
becomes:
x:  [  Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar))]
After step 2: i.e. reducing scope of  the above stmt becomes:
x: [ Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar)) ]
x: [ Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)  hate ( x, Caesar)) ]
54
• Example to demonstrate step 3:- i.e. standardization of
variables.
x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ y: loves( y , x ) ] ]
After step 3 above stmt becomes,
x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z, x ) ] ]
55
• Example to demostrate step 4: Move all quantifiers to the left
without changing their relative order.
•
• x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z, x ) ] ]
• After applying step 4 above stmt becomes:
• x: y: z: [ animal (y)  loves( x , y)  loves( z, x ) ]
• After first 4 processing steps of conversion are carried out
on original statement S, the statement is said to be in
PRENEX NORMAL FORM
56
• Example to demostrate step 5: skolemization ( i.e. elimination
of  quantifier )
y: President (y)
Can be transformed into
President (S1)
where S1 is a function that somehow produces a value that
satisfies President (S1) – S1 called as Skolem constant
• Ex. 2:
y: x: leads ( y , x )
Here value of y that satisfies ‘leads’ depends on particular value
of x hence above stmt can be written as:
x: leads ( f(x) , x )
Where f(x) is skolem function. 57
• Example to demonstrate step 6: dropping prefix 
x: y: z: [ Roman (x)  know ( x, y)  hate( y, z)]
• After prefix dropped becomes,
[ Roman (x)  know ( x, y)  hate( y, z)]
58
• Example to demostrate step 7: Convert the formula into a
conjunction of disjuncts.(CNF)
• Roman (x)  ( ( hate (x , caesar)  loyalto ( x , caesar) )
• Roman (x)  ( ( hate (x , caesar)  loyalto ( x , caesar) )
P Q R
• P  (Q  R )  ( P  Q )  (P  R )
CLAUSE 1 ( Roman (x)  ( hate (x , caesar) ) 
CLAUSE 2 ( Roman (x)  loyalto ( x , caesar) )
59
Unification
• It’s a matching procedure that compares two literals and discovers
whether there exists a set of substitutions that can make them
identical.
• E.g.
Hate( marcus , X) Hate (marcus , caesar)
caesar/ X
e.g. 2.
Hate(X,Y) Hate( john, Z) could be unified as:
John/X and y/z
60
61
Unification:
UNIFY(p, q) = unifier  where SUBST(, p) = SUBST(, q)
x: knows(John, x)  hates(John, x)
knows(John, Jane)
y: knows(y, Leonid)
y: knows(y, mother(y))
x: knows(x, Elizabeth)
UNIFY(knows(John ,x) ,knows(John, Jane)) = {Jane/x}
UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(y, Leonid)) = {Leonid/x, John/y}
UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(y, mother(y))) = {John/y,
mother(John)/x}
UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(x, Elizabeth)) = FAIL
Resolution algorithm
• It is used as inference mechanism.
• Pre-processing steps:
1. Convert the given English sentence into predicate sentence.
2. Not all of these sentences will be in clausal form (CNF).
If any sentence is not in clausal form then convert it into clausal form.
3. Give these sentences (clauses) as an input to resolution
algorithm.
Resolution algorithm steps:
A. Negate the proposition which is to be proved.
i.e. If we have to prove :-
like(tommy , cookies) then assume  like(tommy,cookies)
Add the resultant sentence to the set of sentences from step 3
62
B. Repeat until contradiction is found or no progress can be
made:
i. Select two clauses , call them parent clauses and resolve them
together.
The resultant clause is called resolvant.
e.g. P(x)  Q(x) R(x)   P(X)
Q(x)  R(x)
ii. If resolvant contains empty clause then contradiction has been found.
G(x)  G(x)
E [ EMPTY CLAUSE] 63
iii. If step ii. Results in empty clause , it means our
assumption is wrong
and the original clause (to be proved) has to be true.
64
65
Example
1. Marcus was a man.
2. Marcus was a Pompeian.
3. All Pompeians were Romans.
4. Caesar was a ruler.
5. All Pompeians were either loyal to Caesar or hated him.
6. Every one is loyal to someone.
7. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.
8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar.
1. “Marcus was a man”
------------- 1
2. “Marcus was a Pompeian”
------------- 2
3. “All Pompeian's were Romans”
=> x1: pompeian(x1)  roman(x1).
=> x1:  pompeian(x1)  roman(x1)
----------------- 3
66
man(marcus)
pompeian (marcus)
 pompeian (x1)  roman(x1)
4. “Caesar was a ruler”
---------------- 4
5. “all romans were either loyalto caesar or hated him”
=> x2: roman(x2)  [ loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar) ]
=> x2:  roman(x2)  loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar)
=>  roman(x2)  loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar)
------ 5
67
ruler (caesar)
 roman ( x2)  loyalto (x2 , caesar)  hate (x2 , caesar)
• “Every one is loyal to someone”
=> x3: y1: loyalto(x3, y1).
Let f(x3) be a skolem function then,
=> x3: loyalto(x3, f(x3)).
=> loyalto(x3, f(x3))
---------------- 6
68
loyalto (x3, f(x3))
7. “People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.”
=> x4: y2: [man(x4)  ruler(y2)  tryassassinate(x4, y2) ]
 loyalto(x4, y2)
=> x4: y2:  [man(x4)  ruler(y2)  tryassassinate(x4, y2) ]
 loyalto(x4, y2)
x4: y2:  man(x4)   ruler(y2)   tryassassinate(x4, y2) 
loyalto(x4, y2)
let f(x4) be skolem function then,
=> x4:  man(x4)   ruler(f(x4)) 
 tryassassinate(x4, f(x4))  loyalto(x4, f(x4)) 69
  man(x4)   ruler(f(x4))   tryassassinate(x4, f(x4)) 
loyalto(x4, f(x4))
» ---------- 7
8. “Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar”
tryassassinate(marcus , caesar)
------------ 8
To prove : marcus hate caesar i.e. hate(marcus, caesar)
70

 man( x4)   ruler(f(x4))   tryassassinate(x4, f(x4)) 
loyalto(x4, f(x4))
tryassassinate( marcus , caesar )
• Assume  hate(marcus, caesar)
71
(5)
‫ך‬ hate (marcus , caesar)  roman ( x2)  loyalto (x2 , caesar) 
hate (x2 , caesar)
x2 / marcus
 roman ( marcus)  loyalto (marcus, caesar)
 pompeian (x1)  roman(x1)
(3)
x1 / marcus
(2)
pompeian (marcus)
 pompeian (marcus)  loyalto (marcus, caesar)
loyalto (marcus, caesar)
loyalto (marcus, caesar)
(7)
x4/ marcus
f(x4)/ caesar
 man( marcus)   ruler( caesar )   tryassassinate( marcus , caesar )
(8)
tryassassinate( marcus , caesar )
 man( marcus)   ruler( caesar )
(1)
man( marcus)
 ruler( caesar ) 72
 ruler( caesar )
(4)
ruler( caesar )
E
• Since we get an empty clause i.e. contradiction our assumption
that  hate(marcus, caesar) is false
hence
hate(marcus, caesar) must be true.
73
• Consider the following paragraph:
“ anything anyone eats is called food. Milka likes all kind of
food. Bread is a food. Mango is a food. Alka eats pizza. Alka
eats everything milka eats.”
Translate the following sentences into (WFF) in predicate logic
and then into set of clauses. Using resolution principle answer
the following:
1. Does Milka like pizza?
2. what food Alka eats? [ Question answering]
74
• Solution:
1. “ anything anyone eats is called food.”
x: y: eats(x , y)  food(y)
 x: y:  eats(x , y)  food(y)
  eats(x , y)  food(y) (1)
2. “Milka likes all kind of food”
y1: food(y1)  like(milka , y1)
 y1:  food(y1)  like( milka , y1)
  food(y1)  like( milka , y1) (2)
3. “Bread is a food”
food(bread) (3)
4. “Mango is a food”
food( mango) (4)
75
5. “Alka eats Pizza”
eats( alka, pizza) (5)
6. “Alka eats everything Milka eats”
x1: eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1)
=> x1:  eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1)
=>  eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1) (6)
Question to be answered : 1. “Does Milka likes Pizza ?”
assume : “Milka does not like Pizza”
 like(milka , pizza) (7)
76
 like(milka , pizza) (2)
 food(y1)  like( milka , y1)
pizza/ y1
 food(pizza)
(1)
eats(x , y)  food(y) pizza/ y
 eats(x , pizza)
(5)
eats( alka, pizza)
alka/ x
E
Since  like(milka , pizza) is contradiction like(milka , pizza) is true
77
Question to be answered : 2. “ what food Alka eats ?”
eats( alka, ??)
there exist something which Alka eats we have to find the value of x
x: eats ( alka, x)
Assume : alka does not eat anything
 [x2: eats ( alka, x2)]
=> x2:  eats (alka , x2)
=>  eats (alka , x2) (7)
(7) (5)
 eats (alka , x2) eats( alka, pizza)
pizza/ x2
E
78
• Therefore alka does not eat anything is false and
• Alka eats something is true.
• And x2 stores pizza
• Therefore we conclude :
eats ( alka, ??) answer is “pizza”
79
Instance and Isa relationship
• “ Marcus is a man”
man(marcus)
OR
instance( marcus , man) where marcus is an object/
instance of class ‘man’
“ all pompeians were romans”
x: pompeian(x)  roman(x).
OR
x: instance(x, pompeian)  instance(x, roman).
80
• Isa Predicate :
“ all pompeians were romans”
x: pompeian(x)  roman(x).
OR
x: instance(x, pompeian)  instance(x, roman).------(1)
• Now using isa predicate (1) becomes,
Isa( pompeian , roman)
which means pompeian is a subclass of roman class
but it also requires extra axiom :
x: y: z: isa( y, z)  instance (x , y)  instance ( x , z)
81
82
Using Predicate Logic
• Many English sentences are ambiguous.
• There is often a choice of how to represent
knowledge.
• Obvious information may be necessary for reasoning
• We may not know in advance which statements to
deduce (P or P).
83

More Related Content

What's hot (20)

PPTX
Issues in knowledge representation
Sravanthi Emani
 
PDF
I. AO* SEARCH ALGORITHM
vikas dhakane
 
PPTX
Dempster shafer theory
Dr. C.V. Suresh Babu
 
PPTX
Logics for non monotonic reasoning-ai
ShaishavShah8
 
PPTX
Local search algorithm
Megha Sharma
 
PPTX
Learning in AI
Minakshi Atre
 
PPTX
Unification and Lifting
Megha Sharma
 
PPT
Knowledge Representation & Reasoning
Sajid Marwat
 
PDF
I.BEST FIRST SEARCH IN AI
vikas dhakane
 
PDF
Artificial Intelligence Notes Unit 2
DigiGurukul
 
PDF
State Space Representation and Search
Hitesh Mohapatra
 
PPT
Heuristic Search Techniques {Artificial Intelligence}
FellowBuddy.com
 
PPTX
First order predicate logic (fopl)
chauhankapil
 
PPTX
First order logic
Megha Sharma
 
PDF
5.-Knowledge-Representation-in-AI_010824.pdf
SakshiSingh770619
 
PPTX
AI: Logic in AI
DataminingTools Inc
 
PPTX
Semantic net in AI
ShahDhruv21
 
PPT
Planning
ahmad bassiouny
 
PDF
Production System in AI
Bharat Bhushan
 
PPTX
Problem Formulation in Artificial Inteligence Projects
Dr. C.V. Suresh Babu
 
Issues in knowledge representation
Sravanthi Emani
 
I. AO* SEARCH ALGORITHM
vikas dhakane
 
Dempster shafer theory
Dr. C.V. Suresh Babu
 
Logics for non monotonic reasoning-ai
ShaishavShah8
 
Local search algorithm
Megha Sharma
 
Learning in AI
Minakshi Atre
 
Unification and Lifting
Megha Sharma
 
Knowledge Representation & Reasoning
Sajid Marwat
 
I.BEST FIRST SEARCH IN AI
vikas dhakane
 
Artificial Intelligence Notes Unit 2
DigiGurukul
 
State Space Representation and Search
Hitesh Mohapatra
 
Heuristic Search Techniques {Artificial Intelligence}
FellowBuddy.com
 
First order predicate logic (fopl)
chauhankapil
 
First order logic
Megha Sharma
 
5.-Knowledge-Representation-in-AI_010824.pdf
SakshiSingh770619
 
AI: Logic in AI
DataminingTools Inc
 
Semantic net in AI
ShahDhruv21
 
Planning
ahmad bassiouny
 
Production System in AI
Bharat Bhushan
 
Problem Formulation in Artificial Inteligence Projects
Dr. C.V. Suresh Babu
 

Viewers also liked (10)

PPT
Predicate Logic
giki67
 
PPTX
Knowledge representation in AI
Vishal Singh
 
PPTX
Lecture 21 problem reduction search ao star search
Hema Kashyap
 
PPT
(Radhika) presentation on chapter 2 ai
Radhika Srinivasan
 
PDF
State space search
Timothy Makgato
 
PPTX
Problems problem spaces and search
Amey Kerkar
 
PPT
State Space Search(2)
luzenith_g
 
PPTX
Frames
amitp26
 
PPT
Hill climbing
Mohammad Faizan
 
Predicate Logic
giki67
 
Knowledge representation in AI
Vishal Singh
 
Lecture 21 problem reduction search ao star search
Hema Kashyap
 
(Radhika) presentation on chapter 2 ai
Radhika Srinivasan
 
State space search
Timothy Makgato
 
Problems problem spaces and search
Amey Kerkar
 
State Space Search(2)
luzenith_g
 
Frames
amitp26
 
Hill climbing
Mohammad Faizan
 
Ad

Similar to Knowledge representation and Predicate logic (20)

PPT
Unit III Knowledge Representation in AI K.Sundar,AP/CSE,VEC
sundarKanagaraj1
 
PPT
Artificial intelligent Lec 5-logic
Taymoor Nazmy
 
PDF
Knowledge Representation, Prepositional Logic, Representation and Mapping
PrabhuR97
 
PPTX
Knowledge & logic in Artificial Intelligence.pptx
BisweswarThakur1
 
PPTX
knowledge representation.pptx
SwatiHans10
 
PPT
L03 ai - knowledge representation using logic
Manjula V
 
PPTX
Knnowledge representation and logic lec 11 to lec 15
Subash Chandra Pakhrin
 
PPT
Knowledge representation
Rushdi Shams
 
PDF
16_FirstOrderLogic.p_4_moduleModuleNotespdf
ShylaBg1
 
PPT
PropositionalLogic.ppt
MArunyNandinikkutty
 
PPTX
Foundations of Knowledge Representation in Artificial Intelligence.pptx
kitsenthilkumarcse
 
PPTX
AI_Session 20 Horn clause.pptx
Guru Nanak Technical Institutions
 
PPTX
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning.pptx
MohanKumarP34
 
PPT
Propositional and first order logic - AI
sheetalphougat1
 
PPT
Logic.ppt
syedadamiya
 
PPT
10a.ppt
sunil sharma
 
PDF
Knowledge base artificial intelligence.pdf
jannatulferdous20101
 
PPTX
22PCOAM11 Unit 2:Session 12 Horn Clause.pptx
Guru Nanak Technical Institutions
 
PPT
Propositional and first-order logic different chapters
ines396023
 
PPTX
Drinkfromme.pptx
Ravind8
 
Unit III Knowledge Representation in AI K.Sundar,AP/CSE,VEC
sundarKanagaraj1
 
Artificial intelligent Lec 5-logic
Taymoor Nazmy
 
Knowledge Representation, Prepositional Logic, Representation and Mapping
PrabhuR97
 
Knowledge & logic in Artificial Intelligence.pptx
BisweswarThakur1
 
knowledge representation.pptx
SwatiHans10
 
L03 ai - knowledge representation using logic
Manjula V
 
Knnowledge representation and logic lec 11 to lec 15
Subash Chandra Pakhrin
 
Knowledge representation
Rushdi Shams
 
16_FirstOrderLogic.p_4_moduleModuleNotespdf
ShylaBg1
 
PropositionalLogic.ppt
MArunyNandinikkutty
 
Foundations of Knowledge Representation in Artificial Intelligence.pptx
kitsenthilkumarcse
 
AI_Session 20 Horn clause.pptx
Guru Nanak Technical Institutions
 
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning.pptx
MohanKumarP34
 
Propositional and first order logic - AI
sheetalphougat1
 
Logic.ppt
syedadamiya
 
10a.ppt
sunil sharma
 
Knowledge base artificial intelligence.pdf
jannatulferdous20101
 
22PCOAM11 Unit 2:Session 12 Horn Clause.pptx
Guru Nanak Technical Institutions
 
Propositional and first-order logic different chapters
ines396023
 
Drinkfromme.pptx
Ravind8
 
Ad

Recently uploaded (20)

PPTX
artificial intelligence applications in Geomatics
NawrasShatnawi1
 
PPTX
Worm gear strength and wear calculation as per standard VB Bhandari Databook.
shahveer210504
 
PDF
Set Relation Function Practice session 24.05.2025.pdf
DrStephenStrange4
 
PPTX
GitOps_Without_K8s_Training_detailed git repository
DanialHabibi2
 
PPTX
VITEEE 2026 Exam Details , Important Dates
SonaliSingh127098
 
PPTX
Green Building & Energy Conservation ppt
Sagar Sarangi
 
PPTX
Day2 B2 Best.pptx
helenjenefa1
 
PDF
International Journal of Information Technology Convergence and services (IJI...
ijitcsjournal4
 
PPTX
fatigue in aircraft structures-221113192308-0ad6dc8c.pptx
aviatecofficial
 
PDF
Design Thinking basics for Engineers.pdf
CMR University
 
PDF
AI TECHNIQUES FOR IDENTIFYING ALTERATIONS IN THE HUMAN GUT MICROBIOME IN MULT...
vidyalalltv1
 
PPTX
Server Side Web Development Unit 1 of Nodejs.pptx
sneha852132
 
PDF
Water Industry Process Automation & Control Monthly July 2025
Water Industry Process Automation & Control
 
PPTX
Introduction to Design of Machine Elements
PradeepKumarS27
 
PPTX
原版一样(Acadia毕业证书)加拿大阿卡迪亚大学毕业证办理方法
Taqyea
 
PDF
Electrical Engineer operation Supervisor
ssaruntatapower143
 
PDF
Basic_Concepts_in_Clinical_Biochemistry_2018كيمياء_عملي.pdf
AdelLoin
 
PPTX
Damage of stability of a ship and how its change .pptx
ehamadulhaque
 
PPTX
美国电子版毕业证南卡罗莱纳大学上州分校水印成绩单USC学费发票定做学位证书编号怎么查
Taqyea
 
DOCX
CS-802 (A) BDH Lab manual IPS Academy Indore
thegodhimself05
 
artificial intelligence applications in Geomatics
NawrasShatnawi1
 
Worm gear strength and wear calculation as per standard VB Bhandari Databook.
shahveer210504
 
Set Relation Function Practice session 24.05.2025.pdf
DrStephenStrange4
 
GitOps_Without_K8s_Training_detailed git repository
DanialHabibi2
 
VITEEE 2026 Exam Details , Important Dates
SonaliSingh127098
 
Green Building & Energy Conservation ppt
Sagar Sarangi
 
Day2 B2 Best.pptx
helenjenefa1
 
International Journal of Information Technology Convergence and services (IJI...
ijitcsjournal4
 
fatigue in aircraft structures-221113192308-0ad6dc8c.pptx
aviatecofficial
 
Design Thinking basics for Engineers.pdf
CMR University
 
AI TECHNIQUES FOR IDENTIFYING ALTERATIONS IN THE HUMAN GUT MICROBIOME IN MULT...
vidyalalltv1
 
Server Side Web Development Unit 1 of Nodejs.pptx
sneha852132
 
Water Industry Process Automation & Control Monthly July 2025
Water Industry Process Automation & Control
 
Introduction to Design of Machine Elements
PradeepKumarS27
 
原版一样(Acadia毕业证书)加拿大阿卡迪亚大学毕业证办理方法
Taqyea
 
Electrical Engineer operation Supervisor
ssaruntatapower143
 
Basic_Concepts_in_Clinical_Biochemistry_2018كيمياء_عملي.pdf
AdelLoin
 
Damage of stability of a ship and how its change .pptx
ehamadulhaque
 
美国电子版毕业证南卡罗莱纳大学上州分校水印成绩单USC学费发票定做学位证书编号怎么查
Taqyea
 
CS-802 (A) BDH Lab manual IPS Academy Indore
thegodhimself05
 

Knowledge representation and Predicate logic

  • 1. KNOWLEDGE REPRESENTATION & PREDICATE LOGIC Amey D.S.Kerkar, Asst.Professor, Computer Engineering Dept. Don Bosco College of Engineering, Fatorda-Goa.
  • 2. • To solve complex problems we need: 1. Large amount of knowledge 2. Mechanism for representation and manipulation of existing knowledge to create new solution. Knowledge Representation – Facts: Things we want to represent. Truth in some relevant world. – Representation of facts.
  • 4. Initial facts Internal representations of initial facts desired real reasoning forward representation mapping Final facts Internal representations of final facts backward representation mapping operation of program
  • 5. 5 Representation and Mapping • Spot is a dog • Every dog has a tail Spot has a tail
  • 6. 6 Representation and Mapping • Spot is a dog dog(Spot) • Every dog has a tail x: dog(x)  hastail(x) hastail(Spot) Spot has a tail
  • 7. • Fact-representation mapping is not one-to-one. • Good representation can make a reasoning program trivial. The Multilated Checkerboard Problem “Consider a normal checker board from which two squares, in opposite corners, have been removed. The task is to cover all the remaining squares exactly with donimoes, each of which covers two squares. No overlapping, either of dominoes on top of each other or of dominoes over the boundary of the multilated board are allowed. Can this task be done?” 7
  • 8. 8 Representation and Mapping No. black squares = 30 No. white square = 32
  • 9. Good Knowledge representation should exhibit: 1. Representational adequacy- Ability to represent all kinds of knowledge that are needed in the domain. 2. Inferential adequacy- Ability to manipulate representational structures such that new knowledge can be derived/inferred from the old. 3. Inferential efficiency- Ability to incorporate additional information into an existing knowledge base that can be used to focus the attention of inference mechanisms in the most promising direction. 4. Acquisitional efficiency- Ability to easily acquire new information. 9
  • 10. 10 Approaches to KR 1. Simple relational knowledge: • Provides very weak inferential capabilities. • May serve as the input to powerful inference engines. Fails to infer “which right handed player can best face a particular bowler” . Player Height Weight handed Peter 6-0 180 right Ajay 5-10 170 left John 6-2 215 left Vickey 6-3 205 right
  • 11. 11 Approaches to KR Inheritable knowledge: • Objects are organized into classes and classes are organized in a generalization hierarchy. • Inheritance is a powerful form of inference, but not adequate. • Ex. Property inheritance inference mechanism. Adult male Person isa Peter instance Right handed Tata Consultancy Works_at
  • 12. 12 Approaches to KR Inferential knowledge: • Facts represented in a logical form, which facilitates reasoning. • An inference engine is required. ex. 1. “Marcus is a man” 2. “All men are mortal” Implies: 3. “Marcus is mortal”
  • 13. 13 Approaches to KR Procedural knowledge: • Representation of “how to make it” rather than “what it is”. • May have inferential efficiency, but no inferential adequacy and acquisitional efficiency. • Ex. Writing LISP programs
  • 14. 14 Issues in KR 1. Important Attributes: Isa and instance attributes. 2. Relationships among attributes: inverses, existence in a Isa hierarchy, single-valued attributes, techniques for reasoning about values. 3.Choosing the Granularity: High-level facts may not be adequate for inference. Low-level primitives may require a lot of storage. • Ex: “john spotted sue” [representation: spotted(agent(john),object(sue))] Q1: “who spotted sue?” Ans1: “john”. Q2: “Did john see sue?” Ans2: NO ANSWER!!!! • Add detailed fact: spotted(x,y)-->saw(x,y) then Ans2: “Yes”.
  • 15. • 4.Representing Set of Objects: • 5. finding the right structure as needed.: Ex: word “fly” can have multiple meanings: 1. “John flew to new york” 2. “John flew into a rage” [idiom] 3. “john flew a kite” SELF: Please read frame problem pg. 96-97, Rich & Knight,3rd edition. 15
  • 16. Propositional logic • Statements used in mathematics. • Proposition :is a declarative sentence whose value is either true or false. Examples: • “The sky is blue.” [Atomic Proposition] • “The sky is blue and the plants are green.” [Molecular/Complex Proposition] • “Today is a rainy day” [Atomic Proposition] • “Today is Sunday” [Atomic Proposition] • “ 2*2=4” [Atomic Proposition] 16
  • 17. Terminologies in propositional algebra: Statement: sentence that can be true/false. Properties of statement:  Satisfyability: a sentence is satisfyable if there is an interpretation for which it is true. Eg.”we wear woollen cloths”  Contradiction: if there is no interpretation for which sentence is true. Eg. “Japan is capital of India”  Validity: a sentence is valid if it is true for every interpretation. Eg. “Delhi is the capital of India” 17
  • 19. 19
  • 20. INFERENCE RULES IN PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 1. Idempotent rule: P ˄ P ==> P P ˅ P ==> P 2. Commutative rule: P ˄ Q ==> Q ˄ P P ˅ Q ==> Q ˅ P 3.Associative rule: P ˄ (Q ˄ R) ==> (P ˄ Q) ˄ R P ˅ (Q ˅ R) ==> (P ˅ Q) ˅ R 20
  • 21. 4. Distributive Rule: P ˅ (Q ˄ R) ==> (P ˅ Q) ˄ (P ˅ R) P ˄ (Q ˅ R) ==> (P ˄ Q) ˅ (P ˄ R) 5. De-Morgan’s Rule: ‫(ך‬P ˅ Q) ==> ‫ך‬P ˄ ‫ך‬Q ‫ך‬ (P ˄ Q) ==> ‫ך‬ P ˅ ‫ך‬Q 6. Implication elimination: P  Q => ‫ך‬P ˅ Q 21
  • 22. 7. Bidirectional Implication elimination: ( P  Q ) ==> ( P  Q ) ˄ (Q  P) 8. Contrapositive rule: P  Q => ‫ך‬P  ‫ך‬Q 9. Double Negation rule: ‫(ך‬ ‫ך‬P) => P 10. Absorption Rule: P ˅ ( P ˄ Q) => P P ˄ ( P ˅ Q) => P 22
  • 23. 11.Fundamental identities: P ˄ ‫ך‬ p => F [contradiction] P ˅ ‫ך‬P => T [Tautology] P ˅ T => P P ˅ F => P P ˅ ‫ך‬ T => P P ˄ F => F P ˄ T => P 23
  • 24. 12. Modus Ponens: If P is true and PQ then we can infer Q is also true. P PQ __________ Hence, Q 13. Modus Tollens: If ‫ך‬P is true and PQ then we can infer ‫ך‬Q . ‫ך‬P PQ __________ Hence, ‫ך‬Q 24
  • 25. 14. Chain rule: If pq and qr then pr 15. Disjunctive Syllogism: if ‫ך‬p and p˅q we can infer q is true. 16. AND elimination: Given P and Q are true then we can deduce P and Q seperately: P ˄ Q  P P ˄ Q Q 25
  • 26. 17. AND introduction: Given P and Q are true then we deduce P ˄ Q 18. OR introduction: Given P and Q are true then we can deduce P and Q separately: P P ˅ Q Q P ˅ Q 26
  • 27. • Example: “I will get wet if it rains and I go out of the house” Let Propositions be: W : “I will get wet “ R : “it rains “ S : “I go out of the house” (S ˄ R)  W 27
  • 28. 28 Using Propositional Logic Representing simple facts It is raining RAINING It is sunny SUNNY It is windy WINDY If it is raining, then it is not sunny RAINING  SUNNY
  • 29. Normal Forms in propositional Logic 1. Conjunctive normal form (CNF): e.g. ( P ˅ Q ˅ R ) ˄ (P ˅ Q ) ˄ (P ˅ R ) ˄ P It is conjunction (˄) of disjunctions (˅) Where disjunctions are: 1. ( P ˅ Q ˅ R ) 2. (P ˅ Q ) 3. (P ˅ R ) clauses 4. P 29
  • 30. 2. Disjunctive normal form (DNF): e.g. ( P ˄ Q ˄ R ) ˅ (P ˄ Q ) ˅ (P ˄ R ) ˅ P It is disjunction (˅) of conjunctions (˄) 30
  • 31. Procedure to convert a statement to CNF 1. Eliminate implications and biconditionals using formulas: • ( P  Q ) ==> ( P  Q ) ˄ (Q  P) • P  Q => ‫ך‬P ˅ Q 2. Apply De-Morgan’s Law and reduce NOT symbols so as to bring negations before the atoms. Use: • ‫(ך‬P ˅ Q) ==> ‫ך‬P ˄ ‫ך‬Q • ‫ך‬ (P ˄ Q) ==> ‫ך‬ P ˅ ‫ך‬Q 3. Use distributive and other laws & equivalent formulas to obtain Normal forms. 31
  • 32. Conversion to CNF example Q. Convert into CNF : ( ( PQ )R ) Solution: Step 1: ( ( PQ )R ) ==> ( ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q)R) ==> ‫ך‬ ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q) ˅ R Step 2: ‫ך‬ ( ‫ך‬P ˅ Q) ˅ R ==> (P ˄ ‫ך‬ Q ) ˅ R Step 3: (P ˄ ‫ך‬ Q ) ˅ R ==> ( P ˅ R ) ˄ (‫ך‬ Q ˅ R ) CNF 32
  • 33. Resolution in propositional logic Proof by Refutation / contradiction. • Used for theorem proving / rule of inference. • Method: Say we have to prove proposition A • Assume A to be false i.e. ‫ך‬A • Continue solving the algorithm starting from ‫ך‬A • If you get a contradiction (F) at the end it means your initial assumption i.e. ‫ך‬A is false and hence proposition A must be true. • Clause: disjunction of literals is called clause. 33
  • 34. • How it works? • E.g. “ If it is Hot then it is Humid. If it is humid then it will rain. It is hot.” prove that “ it will rain.” • Solution: • Let us denote these statements with propositions H,O and R: – H: “ It is humid”. – O: “ It is Hot”. And R: “It will rain”. • Formulas corresponding to the sentences are: • 1. “if it is hot then it is humid” [ OH] ==> ‫ך‬O ˅ H • 2. “If it is humid then it will rain”. [ HR] ==> ‫ך‬H ˅ R • 3. “ It is Hot” [ O ] ==> O • • To prove: R. 34
  • 35. • Let us assume “it will NOT rain” [ ‫ך‬R ] • [ ‫ך‬R ] [ ‫ך‬H ˅ R] ‫ך‬H [ ‫ך‬O ˅ H] ‫ך‬ O O E [EMPTY CLAUSE / CONTRADICTION ] 35
  • 36. • Since an empty clause ( E ) has been deduced we say that our assumption is wrong and hence we have proved: “It will rain” Using Prepositional Logic: • Theorem proving is decidable BUT • It Cannot represent objects and quantification. • Hence we go for PREDICATE LOGIC 36
  • 37. PREDICATE LOGIC • Can represent objects and quantification • Theorem proving is semi-decidable 37
  • 38. Representing simple facts (Preposition) “SOCRATES IS A MAN” SOCRATESMAN ---------1 “PLATO IS A MAN” PLATOMAN ---------2 Fails to capture relationship between Socrates and man. We do not get any information about the objects involved Ex: if asked a question : “who is a man?” we cannot get answer. Using Predicate Logic however we can represent above facts as: Man(Socretes) and Man(Plato) 38
  • 39. 39 Using Predicate Logic 1. Marcus was a man. man(Marcus)
  • 40. 40 Using Predicate Logic 2. Marcus was a Pompeian. Pompeian(Marcus)
  • 41. • Quantifiers: • 2 types:- • Universal quantifier () • x: means “for all” x • It is used to represent phrase “ for all”. • It says that something is true for all possible values of a variable. • Ex. “ John loves everyone” • 41
  • 42. • Quantifiers: • 2 types:- • Universal quantifier () • x: means “for all” x • It is used to represent phrase “ for all”. • It says that something is true for all possible values of a variable. • Ex. “ John loves everyone” x: loves(John , x) 42
  • 43. • Existential quantifier (  ): • Used to represent the fact “ there exists some” • Ex: • “some people like reading and hence they gain good knowledge”  x: { [person(x)  like (x , reading)] gain(x, knowledge) } • “lord Haggins has a crown on his head” •  x: crown(x)  onhead (x , Haggins) 43
  • 44. Nested Quantifiers • We can use both  and  seperately • Ex: “ everybody loves somebody ” x: y: loves ( x , y) • Connection between  and  • “ everyone dislikes garlic”  x:  like ( x , garlic )  This can be also said as: “there does not exists someone who likes garlic”  x: like (x, garlic) 44
  • 45. 3. All Romans were either loyal to Caesar or hated him. x: Roman(x)  loyalto (x, Caesar)  hate(x, Caesar) 4. Every one is loyal to someone. x: y: loyalto(x, y) y: x: loyalto(x, y) 5. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to. x: y: person(x)  ruler(y)  tryassassinate(x, y)  loyalto(x, y) 45
  • 46. 46 6. “All Pompeians were Romans” x: Pompeian(x)  Roman(x) 8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar. tryassassinate(Marcus, Caesar)
  • 47. Some more examples • “all indoor games are easy” x: indoor_game( x)  easy(x) • “Rajiv likes only cricket” Like(Rajiv, Cricket) • “Any person who is respected by every person is a king” x:y: { person(x)  person(y)  respects (y ,x) king( x)} 47
  • 48. • “god helps those who helps themselves” x: helps( god, helps(x , x)) • “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone” x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ] everyone who loves all animals z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x Thus the predicate sentence is: x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ] 48 • “god helps those who helps themselves” x: helps( god, helps(x , x)) • “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone” x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ] everyone who loves all animals z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x Thus the predicate sentence is: x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ] • “god helps those who helps themselves” x: helps( god, helps(x , x)) • “everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone” x: [ y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ] everyone who loves all animals z: loves( z , x ) there exist someone z and z loves x Thus the predicate sentence is: x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z , x ) ] ]
  • 49. Computable functions and predicates • “ Marcus was born in 40 A.D” Born( Marcus, 40) • “ All Pompeians died when volcano erupted in 79 A.D” Erupted(volcano, 79)  x: [ Pompeian (x )  Died (x , 79)] • “ no mortal lives longer than 150 years” • How to solve ? • let t1 is time instance 1 and t2 is time instance 2 • We use computable function gt( … , ….) which computes greater than. x: t1: t2: mortal (x)  born ( x, t1)  gt( t2 –t1, 150 )  dead ( x, t2) 49
  • 50. Resolution algorithm in predicate logic • Proof by refutation. • INPUT: Predicate sentences in clausal form (CNF) • (See conversion algo on next slide) • Algorithm steps :- Convert all the propositions of KB to clause form (S). 2. Negate  and convert it to clause form. Add it to S. 3. Repeat until either a contradiction is found or no progress can be made. a. Select two clauses (  P) and (  P). b. Add the resolvent (  ) to S. 50
  • 51. 51 Conversion to Clause Form 1. Eliminate . P  Q  P  Q 2. Reduce the scope of each  to a single term. (P  Q)  P  Q (P  Q)  P  Q x: P  x: P x: p  x: P  P  P 3. Standardize variables so that each quantifier binds a unique variable. (x: P(x))  (x: Q(x))  (x: P(x))  (y: Q(y))
  • 52. 52 4. Move all quantifiers to the left without changing their relative order. (x: P(x))  (y: Q(y))  x: y: (P(x)  (Q(y)) 5. Eliminate  (Skolemization). x: P(x)  P(c) Skolem constant x: y P(x, y)  x: P(x, f(x)) Skolem function 6. Drop . x: P(x)  P(x)
  • 53. 7. Convert the formula into a conjunction of disjuncts. (P  Q)  R  (P  R)  (Q  R) 8. Create a separate clause corresponding to each conjunct. 9. Standardize apart the variables in the set of obtained clauses. 53
  • 54. • Example of conversion: x:  [ Roman (x)  ( Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar))] After step 1: i.e. elimination of  and  the above stmt becomes: x:  [  Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar))] After step 2: i.e. reducing scope of  the above stmt becomes: x: [ Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)   hate ( x, Caesar)) ] x: [ Roman (x)  (Pompeian( x)  hate ( x, Caesar)) ] 54
  • 55. • Example to demonstrate step 3:- i.e. standardization of variables. x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ y: loves( y , x ) ] ] After step 3 above stmt becomes, x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z, x ) ] ] 55
  • 56. • Example to demostrate step 4: Move all quantifiers to the left without changing their relative order. • • x: [ [y: animal (y)  loves( x , y) ]  [ z: loves( z, x ) ] ] • After applying step 4 above stmt becomes: • x: y: z: [ animal (y)  loves( x , y)  loves( z, x ) ] • After first 4 processing steps of conversion are carried out on original statement S, the statement is said to be in PRENEX NORMAL FORM 56
  • 57. • Example to demostrate step 5: skolemization ( i.e. elimination of  quantifier ) y: President (y) Can be transformed into President (S1) where S1 is a function that somehow produces a value that satisfies President (S1) – S1 called as Skolem constant • Ex. 2: y: x: leads ( y , x ) Here value of y that satisfies ‘leads’ depends on particular value of x hence above stmt can be written as: x: leads ( f(x) , x ) Where f(x) is skolem function. 57
  • 58. • Example to demonstrate step 6: dropping prefix  x: y: z: [ Roman (x)  know ( x, y)  hate( y, z)] • After prefix dropped becomes, [ Roman (x)  know ( x, y)  hate( y, z)] 58
  • 59. • Example to demostrate step 7: Convert the formula into a conjunction of disjuncts.(CNF) • Roman (x)  ( ( hate (x , caesar)  loyalto ( x , caesar) ) • Roman (x)  ( ( hate (x , caesar)  loyalto ( x , caesar) ) P Q R • P  (Q  R )  ( P  Q )  (P  R ) CLAUSE 1 ( Roman (x)  ( hate (x , caesar) )  CLAUSE 2 ( Roman (x)  loyalto ( x , caesar) ) 59
  • 60. Unification • It’s a matching procedure that compares two literals and discovers whether there exists a set of substitutions that can make them identical. • E.g. Hate( marcus , X) Hate (marcus , caesar) caesar/ X e.g. 2. Hate(X,Y) Hate( john, Z) could be unified as: John/X and y/z 60
  • 61. 61 Unification: UNIFY(p, q) = unifier  where SUBST(, p) = SUBST(, q) x: knows(John, x)  hates(John, x) knows(John, Jane) y: knows(y, Leonid) y: knows(y, mother(y)) x: knows(x, Elizabeth) UNIFY(knows(John ,x) ,knows(John, Jane)) = {Jane/x} UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(y, Leonid)) = {Leonid/x, John/y} UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(y, mother(y))) = {John/y, mother(John)/x} UNIFY(knows(John, x), knows(x, Elizabeth)) = FAIL
  • 62. Resolution algorithm • It is used as inference mechanism. • Pre-processing steps: 1. Convert the given English sentence into predicate sentence. 2. Not all of these sentences will be in clausal form (CNF). If any sentence is not in clausal form then convert it into clausal form. 3. Give these sentences (clauses) as an input to resolution algorithm. Resolution algorithm steps: A. Negate the proposition which is to be proved. i.e. If we have to prove :- like(tommy , cookies) then assume  like(tommy,cookies) Add the resultant sentence to the set of sentences from step 3 62
  • 63. B. Repeat until contradiction is found or no progress can be made: i. Select two clauses , call them parent clauses and resolve them together. The resultant clause is called resolvant. e.g. P(x)  Q(x) R(x)   P(X) Q(x)  R(x) ii. If resolvant contains empty clause then contradiction has been found. G(x)  G(x) E [ EMPTY CLAUSE] 63
  • 64. iii. If step ii. Results in empty clause , it means our assumption is wrong and the original clause (to be proved) has to be true. 64
  • 65. 65 Example 1. Marcus was a man. 2. Marcus was a Pompeian. 3. All Pompeians were Romans. 4. Caesar was a ruler. 5. All Pompeians were either loyal to Caesar or hated him. 6. Every one is loyal to someone. 7. People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to. 8. Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar.
  • 66. 1. “Marcus was a man” ------------- 1 2. “Marcus was a Pompeian” ------------- 2 3. “All Pompeian's were Romans” => x1: pompeian(x1)  roman(x1). => x1:  pompeian(x1)  roman(x1) ----------------- 3 66 man(marcus) pompeian (marcus)  pompeian (x1)  roman(x1)
  • 67. 4. “Caesar was a ruler” ---------------- 4 5. “all romans were either loyalto caesar or hated him” => x2: roman(x2)  [ loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar) ] => x2:  roman(x2)  loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar) =>  roman(x2)  loyalto(x2 , caesar)  hate(x2 , caesar) ------ 5 67 ruler (caesar)  roman ( x2)  loyalto (x2 , caesar)  hate (x2 , caesar)
  • 68. • “Every one is loyal to someone” => x3: y1: loyalto(x3, y1). Let f(x3) be a skolem function then, => x3: loyalto(x3, f(x3)). => loyalto(x3, f(x3)) ---------------- 6 68 loyalto (x3, f(x3))
  • 69. 7. “People only try to assassinate rulers they are not loyal to.” => x4: y2: [man(x4)  ruler(y2)  tryassassinate(x4, y2) ]  loyalto(x4, y2) => x4: y2:  [man(x4)  ruler(y2)  tryassassinate(x4, y2) ]  loyalto(x4, y2) x4: y2:  man(x4)   ruler(y2)   tryassassinate(x4, y2)  loyalto(x4, y2) let f(x4) be skolem function then, => x4:  man(x4)   ruler(f(x4))   tryassassinate(x4, f(x4))  loyalto(x4, f(x4)) 69
  • 70.   man(x4)   ruler(f(x4))   tryassassinate(x4, f(x4))  loyalto(x4, f(x4)) » ---------- 7 8. “Marcus tried to assassinate Caesar” tryassassinate(marcus , caesar) ------------ 8 To prove : marcus hate caesar i.e. hate(marcus, caesar) 70   man( x4)   ruler(f(x4))   tryassassinate(x4, f(x4))  loyalto(x4, f(x4)) tryassassinate( marcus , caesar )
  • 71. • Assume  hate(marcus, caesar) 71 (5) ‫ך‬ hate (marcus , caesar)  roman ( x2)  loyalto (x2 , caesar)  hate (x2 , caesar) x2 / marcus  roman ( marcus)  loyalto (marcus, caesar)  pompeian (x1)  roman(x1) (3) x1 / marcus (2) pompeian (marcus)  pompeian (marcus)  loyalto (marcus, caesar) loyalto (marcus, caesar)
  • 72. loyalto (marcus, caesar) (7) x4/ marcus f(x4)/ caesar  man( marcus)   ruler( caesar )   tryassassinate( marcus , caesar ) (8) tryassassinate( marcus , caesar )  man( marcus)   ruler( caesar ) (1) man( marcus)  ruler( caesar ) 72
  • 73.  ruler( caesar ) (4) ruler( caesar ) E • Since we get an empty clause i.e. contradiction our assumption that  hate(marcus, caesar) is false hence hate(marcus, caesar) must be true. 73
  • 74. • Consider the following paragraph: “ anything anyone eats is called food. Milka likes all kind of food. Bread is a food. Mango is a food. Alka eats pizza. Alka eats everything milka eats.” Translate the following sentences into (WFF) in predicate logic and then into set of clauses. Using resolution principle answer the following: 1. Does Milka like pizza? 2. what food Alka eats? [ Question answering] 74
  • 75. • Solution: 1. “ anything anyone eats is called food.” x: y: eats(x , y)  food(y)  x: y:  eats(x , y)  food(y)   eats(x , y)  food(y) (1) 2. “Milka likes all kind of food” y1: food(y1)  like(milka , y1)  y1:  food(y1)  like( milka , y1)   food(y1)  like( milka , y1) (2) 3. “Bread is a food” food(bread) (3) 4. “Mango is a food” food( mango) (4) 75
  • 76. 5. “Alka eats Pizza” eats( alka, pizza) (5) 6. “Alka eats everything Milka eats” x1: eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1) => x1:  eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1) =>  eats(milka , x1)  eats(alka, x1) (6) Question to be answered : 1. “Does Milka likes Pizza ?” assume : “Milka does not like Pizza”  like(milka , pizza) (7) 76
  • 77.  like(milka , pizza) (2)  food(y1)  like( milka , y1) pizza/ y1  food(pizza) (1) eats(x , y)  food(y) pizza/ y  eats(x , pizza) (5) eats( alka, pizza) alka/ x E Since  like(milka , pizza) is contradiction like(milka , pizza) is true 77
  • 78. Question to be answered : 2. “ what food Alka eats ?” eats( alka, ??) there exist something which Alka eats we have to find the value of x x: eats ( alka, x) Assume : alka does not eat anything  [x2: eats ( alka, x2)] => x2:  eats (alka , x2) =>  eats (alka , x2) (7) (7) (5)  eats (alka , x2) eats( alka, pizza) pizza/ x2 E 78
  • 79. • Therefore alka does not eat anything is false and • Alka eats something is true. • And x2 stores pizza • Therefore we conclude : eats ( alka, ??) answer is “pizza” 79
  • 80. Instance and Isa relationship • “ Marcus is a man” man(marcus) OR instance( marcus , man) where marcus is an object/ instance of class ‘man’ “ all pompeians were romans” x: pompeian(x)  roman(x). OR x: instance(x, pompeian)  instance(x, roman). 80
  • 81. • Isa Predicate : “ all pompeians were romans” x: pompeian(x)  roman(x). OR x: instance(x, pompeian)  instance(x, roman).------(1) • Now using isa predicate (1) becomes, Isa( pompeian , roman) which means pompeian is a subclass of roman class but it also requires extra axiom : x: y: z: isa( y, z)  instance (x , y)  instance ( x , z) 81
  • 82. 82 Using Predicate Logic • Many English sentences are ambiguous. • There is often a choice of how to represent knowledge. • Obvious information may be necessary for reasoning • We may not know in advance which statements to deduce (P or P).
  • 83. 83